A soul catcher is a piece of incised bear femur decorated with animal heads. Used
by the Tsimshian people of the Pacific Northwest, it is plugged with cedar bark on
both ends in order to catch and contain that ephemeral thing that Western Europeans
have called ‘the soul’ – a lost soul or an evil spirit. While the soul catcher might
strike us today as the cultural artefact of an animistic religious system, or perhaps
as a superstitious relic, it resembles in both its form and its function a number
of objects central to the modern mind and brain sciences. Many of these technologies
could also in their way be labelled ‘soul catchers’ because they attempt to capture,
render visible for study, and manipulate what otherwise eludes our physical grasp.
With what justification might one consider voodoo and shamanism the products of naivety
or deception, but not the devices and instruments, practices and routines used in
Western science, which equally try to catch ‘souls’: the unconscious, the mind of
the child, or the activity of a brain in a scanner?
This is not to downplay differences between these technologies of ‘soul catching’,
which are indeed impossible to miss. Even a short glance reveals differences of scale,
of cultural authority and plausibility, differences which reflect many of the oppositions
that structure the modern world: science versus superstition, mainstream versus marginal,
and the finer differentiations between psychoanalysis, psychology, neurology, brain
science, and criminology, amongst others. Nevertheless, in this special issue, we
use the anthropological comparison to the soul catcher in order to open up new perspectives
on the history of the contemporary mind sciences and their material cultures. Casting
the machines and apparatuses of the mind and ‘neuro’ sciences as soul catchers, we
hope to draw attention to the way in which they use material means to examine what
is often taken to be immaterial. What status do we attribute to the souls that they
conjure up? How do they render those souls tangible, measurable, or treatable?
1
Material Culture
‘Matter matters.’ John Law’s observation concisely expresses the insight that has
fuelled the interest in the ‘material culture’ of science. Since the mid 1980s, when
Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer placed them at the centre of their investigations
in Leviathan and the Air Pump, scholars have investigated the ways in which instruments
and scientific practice have produced and shaped epistemic objects.
1
Drawing inspiration from the methodologies of anthropology, they have investigated
the locations where scientific research takes place, examining material culture in
order to analyse what has been called the ‘manufacture of knowledge’ (Knorr-Cetina)
and ‘laboratory life’ (Latour and Woolgar).
2
In a number of micro-studies, these scholars and others have brought to light the
myriad relations between scientists, their epistemic objects, and laboratory equipment
used as ‘inscription devices’.
3
As proponents of the sociology of scientific knowledge (SSK), Shapin and Schaffer
have been closely associated with social constructivism.
4
But the appeal to material culture has been used most often to temper social constructivism’s
more radical claims. An investigation of the apparatuses central to scientific research
brings to light the material constraints and (contingent) limits of social construction.
It thus curtails a tendency towards radical and self-destructive relativism without
thereby entailing the embrace of naive realism.
About a third of a century after these early explorations, the historical study of
material culture can boast a long pedigree and comprises multiple, sometimes conflicting,
programs of research. But it is still possible to sketch out several key arguments
that have structured the field from its earliest days:
1. Moving beyond the textual sources that have often guided research, scholars interested
in material culture focus on scientific routines and practices. Scientific knowledge,
they argue, is not made but performed. It becomes real ‘in action’. By emphasising
the importance of such practice, scholars have indicated the untenability of distinctions
such as that between the ‘strictly scientific’ and the ‘purely social’, or that between
brain scanners and indigenous soul catchers. The practices that produce and confirm
knowledge are not restricted to the laboratory but can be found in a wide variety
of locales.
2. Once established, such practices tend to stabilise and reproduce themselves. The
integrated package of scientists and technicians, their instruments, and their recording
devices become what Latour has called ‘immutable mobiles’, which can be moved from
one setting to another without losing their structure and coherence. They account
in this way for the stabilities and continuities in scientific investigations across
space and time. To understand scientific knowledge and realities, we have to pay attention
to these mobiles and their material aspects, examining the human relationships they
create and the forms of knowing they allow.
3. An emphasis on material culture has produced close affinities between the history
of science and neighbouring fields. The ideas developed in media studies, particularly
those of Friedrich Kittler, have been influential in the German-speaking history of
science.
5
Kittler’s concept of the ‘Aufschreibesystem’ (inscription system) allows for the reconstruction
of the various connections between humans, apparatuses, and inscription devices as
a condition of the modern life sciences.
6
Similarly, as we have seen, material culture opens up points of contact between the
history of science and anthropology, which has long examined the meaning and uses
of objects as a way to understand society.
2
The Mind Sciences and Material Culture
While an analysis of material culture has been widely influential in the histories
of science and medicine, it seems to reach a limit case in the history of the mind
sciences. The confluence of the two raises a host of important and difficult questions:
How does the mind interact with the world? How have scientists understood the interaction
between the two? How have they constructed material apparatuses to record the workings
of the mind? And in what ways has this material culture informed scientific developments?
In its most authoritative formulations, at least, the historiography of the mind sciences
has not offered rigorous answers to these questions. We can explain this lacuna by
the way in which the major strands of that history – one participating predominantly
in broader trends within the history of medicine, the other in trends within the history
of science – have responded to the historiographical choices of the scholarship in
the first half of the twentieth century. Reacting to its elitism, its moral optimism
about scientific development, or to its emphasis on intellectual history as the prime
driver, the history of the mind and brain sciences has not yet posed the problem of
soul catching.
At least from the perspective of historians in the 1960s and beyond, early twentieth-century
histories of the mind sciences focused excessively on great men and their ideas, presenting
heroic narratives about the discovery of truths, structured teleologically by ideals
about how the sciences of mind and brain should be performed. Most famously, in 1941,
psychoanalyst-historian Gregory Zilboorg presented the history of psychiatry as a
series of medicalisations through which the superstition of the Middle Ages was overcome
to produce a positivist present.
7
The result was a story of ‘progress’. Over time, witchcraft came to be recognised
as what it truly was: mental illness.
These narratives provoked a robust reaction in the mid-twentieth century on the part
of historians of psychiatry participating in the ‘social turn’ in the history of medicine.
Taking its cue from Marxism, the ‘new social history of medicine’ turned away from
the study of great men and their ideas and rather sought to recover the experiences
of non-elites and analyse the social impact of medicine as well as social responses
to disease.
8
Though these new forms of history often presented themselves as (Marxist) materialist
accounts, they tended to pass over material culture and remained focused on the questions
and problems of the old orthodoxy. As Alexandra Bacopoulos-Viau and Aude Fauvel have
shown in a recent and thoughtful special issue of this journal, historians of psychiatry
responded to Roy Porter’s programmatic 1985 essay ‘The Patient’s View: Doing Medical
History from Below’ by paying attention to new sources, the roles of gender and class,
and to non-Western perspectives, amongst others. Often this work was mobilised as
social criticism, a trend recently picked up by ‘Mad Studies’.
9
In all of this, scholars foregrounded human subjectivity and agency. It is telling
that, in the special issue, material culture is primarily considered as a means by
which we are able to hear the patient’s voice.
A second line of criticism attacked the teleology implicit in the older generation’s
account. Historians like Andrew Scull and David Rothman took inspiration from Michel
Foucault’s treatment of the psychiatric asylum, analysing the ways in which knowledge
was complicit in structures of power.
10
Taking as their target the Whiggish view of scientific progress, these historians
were concerned predominantly with breaking the connection between knowledge and liberation,
and so they directed their attention to the social ramifications of the medicine of
the mind. And even as some of these works have come under attack, these questions
have remained at the forefront of debate. Jack Pressman’s history of lobotomy from
1998 (which can be taken as representative of a broader trend in the history of the
mind sciences
11
) responded both to the social history of medicine and to Foucault; in contradistinction
to them, he emphasised the beneficial aspects of somatic treatment in psychiatry.
But, as before, Pressman pitched his analysis at the level of social relations.
12
Though not participating directly in the same developments of the history of medicine,
the scholarship in the history of psychology has adopted a similar set of questions.
The work on psychological testing, for instance – histories of intelligence,
13
personality,
14
and projective testing
15
– have often assumed the task of revealing these practices’ political meanings and
de-humanising potential. Similarly, historians who have examined technologies for
capturing dreams and detecting lies were largely interested in the moralising and
coercive aspects of these endeavours.
16
The avoidance of the question of soul catching is perhaps more surprising in a second
strand of the history of the mind and brain sciences, a strand which participates
more directly in the turn towards material culture. Most immediately relevant for
us is the work of Michael Hagner, Cornelius Borck, and Andreas Mayer, who all follow
the lead of Hans-Jörg Rheinberger and his analysis of ‘experimental systems’.
17
In ‘The Electrical Excitability of the Brain’, Hagner demonstrates how the discussion
of cerebral localisation in Germany grew out of physician Eduard Hitzig’s finding
during electrotherapy that currents applied behind the human ear caused eye movements.
18
In his work on the history of the inscription of mental events, Cornelius Borck shows
how for Hans Berger the EEG transformed changes in the electrical potential of the
brain into an ‘epistemic thing’,
19
allowing thought to be visualised.
20
So, too, Andreas Mayer situates psychoanalysis within a broader scientific culture
of what he calls the ‘experimentalisation of the unconscious’, of which hypnosis was
a major part; psychoanalysis should be understood as a successor to the stage and
laboratory technique of hypnosis.
21
But while these works emphasise the materiality of experimental systems, they haven’t
foregrounded the problem of soul catching. Hagner, Borck, and Meyer direct their efforts
primarily against the emphasis on intellectual history seen in the scholarly literature
from the first half of the twentieth century. They want to show that the production
of scientific knowledge is as much, if not more, the result of experimental systems
as the logic of ideas. Their work has thus been focused predominantly on adjudicating
claims of responsibility and causality in scientific development and not on the questions
raised by the apparent mismatch between the immaterial mind and the material devices
designed to grasp it.
3
Catching Souls
In this special issue, the papers focus on this missed opportunity for thinking through
the relationship between the history of the mind sciences and material culture. All
begin their reflections by posing this relationship as a problem and guide their reflections
by the examination of one set of material apparatuses. The analyses raise a number
of issues:
First, as the provocation of our title makes clear, the analysis of soul catching
challenges the narratives of scientification and secularisation that have guided old
accounts of the mind sciences. It requires us to think about how to draw the line
between the scientific and the animistic, to determine what separates the equipment
and technologies of the modern mind sciences from those that one might define as occult.
In this way, it can draw attention to a lingering persistence of the spiritual in
the most seemingly modern of sciences or the way in which animistic and modern technologies
can come together in unexpected ways. We might go further. Perhaps the soul catcher
doesn’t simply alert us to the way in which animistic elements can persist within
modern biomedicine; perhaps it shows that they are inextricably connected. Several
of the papers suggest that the soul catcher analogy is powerful because it points
to an irreducible contamination of the supposedly somatic principles of modern medicine.
The argument here is that the instruments and material culture of the modern mind
and brain sciences function like soul catchers because they are grappling with the
same problem: how to make the invisible visible, to capture and study that which seems
fleeting and ethereal. In this vein, Nicolas Pethes shows how Hippolyte Baraduc’s
soul photography in late nineteenth-century Paris informed contemporaneous psychology
and medicine and inspired the aesthetics of the avant-garde (‘Psychicones: Visual
Traces of the Soul in Late Nineteenth-Century Fluidic Photography’). Non-mimetic and
abstract in character, soul photography was particularly appealing at a time when
the soul itself was imagined as abstract. Cornelius Borck in ‘Animating Brains’ examines
EEG and neuroimaging to illustrate how a naturalising paradigm requires hybridisation,
the uneasy appeal to the immaterial mind it otherwise seems to exclude. Taking the
recent controversy around ‘Voodoo Correlations in Social Neuroscience’ as his starting
point, Borck shows how these machines establish ‘natural objects with more-than-natural
qualities’.
There is, however, a second way of thinking about the soul catcher, one that, initially
at least, appears to be diametrically opposed to this last interpretation. The soul
catcher isn’t about the persistent trace of the spiritual, the ghost in the machine:
it is rather a ghost buster. The soul catchers of the American Northwest attempted
to imprison an evil spirit. Do the soul catchers of modern science also try to reduce,
contain, or tame the soul? Are they perhaps technologies for refusing it any autonomous
ontological status? In this, technological complexity is not decisive per se. As Katja
Guenther shows in her contribution (‘It’s All Done With Mirrors’: V.S. Ramachandran
and the Material Culture of Phantom Limb Research’), the neuroscientist Vilayanur
S. Ramachandran working at the University of California, San Diego in the 1990s thought
that the mirror, one of the simplest pieces of neuroscientific equipment, could be
used to manipulate mental representations of the body without departing from a materialist
framework. Ramachandran was led to this conclusion by the success of his mirror therapy
in treating phantom limb pain and a consideration of new research into mirror neurons.
Even words are able to produce material effects. Such is the argument in Scott Phelps’s
paper, ‘Brain Ways: Meynert, Bachelard, and the Material Imagination of the Inner
Life’. Phelps is interested in the way in which the Austrian psychiatrist Theodor
Meynert used ‘material images’ (Bachelard), such as ‘roots’, ‘fibers’, or ‘pathways’
to support the argument that the mind was materially grounded: that, in Phelps’s words,
‘the interior of the brain was the interior of the mind’.
There is a third aspect of the soul catcher that emerges from our analyses. The soul
catcher is never simply about the individual scientist or patient. Rather, it mediates
a relationship. Catching or treating a soul is always a social activity. It wants
to make that soul public, to open up the solipsistic individual to other people, to
render what is private readable. As Alicia Puglionesi argues in ‘Drawing as Instrument/Drawings
as Evidence: Capturing Mental Processes with Pencil and Paper’, drawing was used as
an objective access to thought processes in the three contexts between 1880 and the
1930s that she explores: the child study movement, psychical research, and neuropathology.
In drawing, the mind revealed itself; thus, sketches could mediate between different
disciplines and groups of professionals as well as the relationship between doctor
and patient.
In his 1962 work The Savage Mind, Claude Lévi-Strauss used anthropology to challenge
the opposition between ‘primitive’ thought and modern rationalism.
22
The ‘savage mind’ was not fundamentally different from the modern scientific one;
rather, it revealed most clearly the way thought in general was structured. Such an
approach has also proven valuable in the mind and brain sciences.
23
Here, however, we are using the anthropological reference for a subtly different reason.
The soul catcher analogy does not demonstrate how ‘primitive’ thought is more familiar
than we tend to believe – how seemingly mythical totems were ‘good for thinking’.
Rather it draws our attention to the ways in which modern science is less familiar,
more mysterious than we normally assume. To defamiliarise the machines and apparatuses
of the modern mind sciences would be to remind us that they are not simply concerned
with optical illusions or blood flows in the brain. Perhaps they are just the latest
in a long line of instruments designed to catch the soul.