5
views
0
recommends
+1 Recommend
0 collections
    0
    shares
      • Record: found
      • Abstract: found
      • Article: found
      Is Open Access

      Ethics of Short-Term Experiences in Global Health: Engaging Skeptics of Change

      editorial
      , PhD 1
      Annals of Global Health
      Ubiquity Press

      Read this article at

      Bookmark
          There is no author summary for this article yet. Authors can add summaries to their articles on ScienceOpen to make them more accessible to a non-specialist audience.

          Abstract

          Many Tools to Fix the Problem Short-term experiences in global health (STEGHs) have rightly been the subject of increased scrutiny [1], and many scholars have provided critiques and recommendations as to how they might be improved [2 3]. Rowthorn and colleagues present the most robust analysis of where STEGHs move beyond being unethical to also being illegal [4]. Raising awareness of how STEGHs can violate the law is an important approach to correcting unethical behaviors. Another tool, as the authors also suggest, is the soft power of professional norms and global standards, which may involve “naming and shaming” violators or creating accreditation programs to STEGHs. In addition, I would suggest that those who wish to change behavior must directly engage with those who may not entirely agree that these experiences need significant changes. Engagement with Skeptics of Change Despite the fact that many will be horrified by the anecdotes shared by Rowthorn and colleagues, for many, the solution is not immediately obvious. This is because skeptics of change hold competing interests that create, in their minds, genuine dilemmas. Below, I raise common objections to the idea that STEGHs need wholesale change and offer a very brief response to each. (1) Some care is better than no care. Although it is not ideal to have people performing outside the scope of their formal training, patients and the community are better off than they otherwise would be. This is the most common defense of STEGHs in their current form. And it relies on a narrow utilitarian calculation that negative patient outcomes are outweighed by the positive ones. I have never seen a credible empirical assessment of this claim [5]. And the often-hidden negative outcomes, such as creating a belief among host communities that local providers are not effective or providing short-term solutions to long-term health problems, are difficult to calculate. But even if the net utility was positive, such a position fails to consider other values we hold dear in health care. For example, this approach conditions providers and teaches students that unequal treatment of patients is acceptable and that the poor are fortunate to get whatever they can, even if it violates standards of care. That cannot help but shape the way they see the world. On the other hand, the above claim is ethically acceptable in times of emergency. Natural or other disasters create situations wherein those without proper training do whatever good they can, even if it causes some harm along the way. Some may claim that the lack of health care in areas visited by STEGHs is equivalent to an emergency situation, thus justifying extraordinary action. However, most STEGHs have long-term, established relationships with local communities. If they had invested in public health infrastructure, health education, and health profession training, the emergency conditions would have long ago been resolved. (2) If host communities did not want STEGHs acting as they do, they would enforce different standards. Since host communities accept actions of STEGHs, that should be enough. I am sympathetic to this argument because I believe host communities should generally be given the power to deem what is acceptable and what is not. However, this position generally ignores two things. First, as Rowthorn and colleagues observe, many countries have already stated what is acceptable and what is not. Many of them have licensure laws that volunteers ignore. A country’s lack of the capacity to enforce its laws does not mean its will should be dismissed. Second, this claim ignores the power differential that prevails between volunteers and host organizations. Many communities rely on the funds spent by volunteers – on lodging, transportation, food, souvenirs, and more. And many host organization’s employees are dependent upon a steady stream of volunteers for their livelihood. Even more, in many cultures, being good hosts is a central value and so it would be anathema to critique a guest, even when their actions are harmful. Therefore, this argument can only be credible in situations where we are confident that power and cultural norms are not shaping the dynamic between volunteers and host organizations. (3) These are important experiences for volunteers and often lead to life-long commitments to service in the global south. If we make it less attractive, we reduce the connections that lead to long-term relationships. We should provide opportunities that engender solidarity across communities. Yet instead of solidarity, many STEGHs establish a disposition of volunteer as savior or tourist. This is especially true when medical professionals model unethical or illegal behavior for students. We should ensure volunteer experiences are creating the habits that we want replicated over the long-term, which includes following best practices even when they seem inconvenient [6]. Otherwise, we might be encouraging life-long commitments, but they will not be the kind of commitments that help transform the communities in need. Many of these experiences provide greater benefit to the volunteers than to the communities served. Ignoring that reality is, in part, what makes these experiences so troubling. In my opinion, STEGHs would have far less to prove if they confronted the false narrative that they are primarily altruistic. Conclusion Many people agree with the three statements above and critics of STEGHs dismiss them at the expense of making change more likely. The simple fact that so many organizations and individuals continue to behave in defiance of the law and in violation of ethical norms means that there are countervailing values that must be dislodged. Engaging with these skeptics is an important tool, alongside those suggested by Rowthorn and colleagues, to making STEGHs not only comply with legal standards, but also align with the ethical norms of health care practice.

          Related collections

          Most cited references5

          • Record: found
          • Abstract: found
          • Article: not found

          Short-term medical service trips: a systematic review of the evidence.

          Short-term medical service trips (MSTs) aim to address unmet health care needs of low- and middle-income countries. The lack of critically reviewed empirical evidence of activities and outcomes is a concern. Developing evidence-based recommendations for health care delivery requires systematic research review. I focused on MST publications with empirical results. Searches in May 2013 identified 67 studies published since 1993, only 6% of the published articles on the topic in the past 20 years. Nearly 80% reported on surgical trips. Although the MST field is growing, its medical literature lags behind, with nearly all of the scholarly publications lacking significant data collection. By incorporating data collection into service trips, groups can validate practices and provide information about areas needing improvement.
            Bookmark
            • Record: found
            • Abstract: found
            • Article: found
            Is Open Access

            Brain Gains: a literature review of medical missions to low and middle-income countries

            Background Healthcare professionals’ participation in short-term medical missions to low and middle income countries (LMIC) to provide healthcare has become common over the past 50 years yet little is known about the quantity and quality of these missions. The aim of this study was to review medical mission publications over 25 years to better understand missions and their potential impact on health systems in LMICs. Methods A literature review was conducted by searching Medline for articles published from 1985–2009 about medical missions to LMICs, revealing 2512 publications. Exclusion criteria such as receiving country and mission length were applied, leaving 230 relevant articles. A data extraction sheet was used to collect information, including sending/receiving countries and funding source. Results The majority of articles were descriptive and lacked contextual or theoretical analysis. Most missions were short-term (1 day – 1 month). The most common sending countries were the U.S. and Canada. The top destination country was Honduras, while regionally Africa received the highest number of missions. Health care professionals typically responded to presenting health needs, ranging from primary care to surgical relief. Cleft lip/palate surgeries were the next most common type of care provided. Conclusions Based on the articles reviewed, there is significant scope for improvement in mission planning, monitoring and evaluation as well as global and/or national policies regarding foreign medical missions. To promote optimum performance by mission staff, training in such areas as cross-cultural communication and contextual realities of mission sites should be provided. With the large number of missions conducted worldwide, efforts to ensure efficacy, harmonisation with existing government programming and transparency are needed.
              Bookmark
              • Record: found
              • Abstract: found
              • Article: found
              Is Open Access

              More harm than good? The questionable ethics of medical volunteering and international student placements

              It has been argued that much of international medical volunteering is done for the wrong reasons, in that local people serve as a means to meet volunteers’ needs, or for the right reasons but ignorance and ill-preparedness harm the intended beneficiaries, often without volunteers’ grasp of the damage caused. The literature on ethical concerns in medical volunteering has grown tremendously over the last years highlighting the need for appropriate guidelines. These same concerns, however, and an appreciation of the reasons why current aid paradigms are flawed, can serve as indicators on how to change existing practices to ensure a better outcome for those who are in need of help. Such paradigm change envisages medical assistance in the spirit of solidarity, social justice, equality, and collegial collaboration.
                Bookmark

                Author and article information

                Contributors
                Journal
                Ann Glob Health
                Ann Glob Health
                2214-9996
                Annals of Global Health
                Ubiquity Press
                2214-9996
                17 June 2019
                2019
                : 85
                : 1
                : 82
                Affiliations
                [1 ]Department of Health Management and Policy, Saint Louis University School of Public Health, US
                Article
                10.5334/aogh.2529
                6634420
                31225958
                1c72c008-a32b-4013-9e19-be703a6c5074
                Copyright: © 2019 The Author(s)

                This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (CC-BY 4.0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited. See http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.

                History
                Categories
                Editorial

                Comments

                Comment on this article