40
views
0
recommends
+1 Recommend
0 collections
    6
    shares
      • Record: found
      • Abstract: found
      • Article: found
      Is Open Access

      Conditions for minimal intelligence across eukaryota: a cognitive science perspective

      editorial

      Read this article at

      Bookmark
          There is no author summary for this article yet. Authors can add summaries to their articles on ScienceOpen to make them more accessible to a non-specialist audience.

          Abstract

          What is minimal intelligence? Generally speaking, our understanding of intelligence has to do with sets of biological functions of organisms that exhibit a degree of flexibility against contingencies in their environment-induced behavioral repertoire. In principle, sensory perception, sensory-motor coordination, basic forms of learning and memory, decision-making and problem solving, are all marks of minimal intelligence subject to scrutiny with the toolkit of the cognitive sciences. The bottom line is that an appraisal of the behavioral repertoire of eukaryotes, and of the organizational features that sustain it, resists an interpretation in reactive, non-cognitive, terms. Despite the manifest diversity in the behavior of animals, plants, fungi and protists, and the functional specialization of different eukaryote cells, cellular organization based on the division into a nucleus and a cytoplasm allows for the genomic collaboration in the overall guidance of the response patterns to be observed, for example, in growth and development. However, understanding the expression of overt behavior at the level of its eukaryote cellular basis, or unearthing connections between behavior and genes, are but one piece of the puzzle. The research program requires, not only that we assess the cellular changes to be associated with, say, behavioral flexibility, but also the direct comparison across organisms with an eye to highlighting similarities and differences in the behavior of eukaryotes. The objective is ultimately to obtain a general picture of the capacity of organisms to solve problems in novel, often stressful, situations that enable them to deal with variable and complex environmental circumstances. By anchoring and comparing minimal, and yet robust, forms of behavior both functionally and structurally, the ability of organisms to learn from previous experiences, to predict future stresses, and to shape as well as to select suitable environments will be better appraised. The fact that eukaryotes effectively exhibit minimal forms of intelligence might not be breaking news. In effect, the list of minimally intelligent organisms may well include E.coli and other prokaryotes (Lyon, 2007; Richardson, 2012, 2013). Possible examples of bacterial intelligence include communication, decision-making, cooperative behavior, and social intelligence as important survival strategies (Ben-Jacob et al., 2004; Hellingwerf, 2005; Lyon, 2007; Shapiro, 2007; Ben-Jacob, 2014). Coordination is needed, and cellular electrical excitability for the purpose of the transmission of information relies upon the capacity of organisms to conduct signals from receptor to effector sites. As a matter of fact, so-called neuroid conduction (“the propagation of electrical events in of non-nervous, nonmuscular cells,” see Mackie, 1970, p. 319) takes place in protists and plants. Animal nervous systems do organize signaling systems, ion channels, or synapses in more complex forms, but the basic components are already present in precursor organisms (see Calvo, forthcoming, and references therein). Although minimal intelligence is likely to be present already in Eubacteria and Archaea (Crespi, 2001; Shapiro, 2007; Baluska and Mancuso, 2009), for present purposes we exclusively consider discussion of minimal intelligence within Eukarya. This includes both unicellular and multicellular organisms. These organisms have simple nervous systems or lack a nervous system altogether (Jennings, 1923). In order to maintain a sharp focus on minimal forms of intelligence, we exclude chordates (e.g., mammals, fish, reptiles, and birds). How does research on minimal intelligence contribute to cognitive science? Our attempt is to: Parcel out a set of conditions for minimal intelligence across living systems; Understand what sort of behavioral and biological properties and capacities warrant the ascription of a form of minimal intelligence to eukaryotes; and Build-up the concept of minimal intelligence from simpler to more complex life forms. Our strategy is orthogonal to other attempts found in the literature. Attempts inspired by “dual-process” theories (Evans and Frankish, 2009), for instance, assume that intelligence in general is implemented by two markedly different processing subsystems. One older subsystem (evolutionary speaking) puts us in close relation to our fellow non-human animals, and allows for basic tasks such as pattern-recognition. Another more recent subsystem would subserve abstract reasoning and other competencies of that ilk (Stanovich and West, 2000). Approaches of this sort mark a divide between minimal forms of intelligence, those that are implemented by a more primitive subsystem, and those of full blown intelligence that are implemented by a more recently evolved subsystem. Our objective is to understand how much can be revealed about higher-level cognition before a dual-processing dichotomy needs to be called for in the first place. This does not imply that intelligence, writ large, may end up requiring a divide-and-rule strategy. That is an open question. We aim to assess how much of intelligent behavior can be accounted for by positing overarching sets of mechanisms which can be generally ascribed as cognition scales up. Our rationale is that, contrary to conventional wisdom, we do not understand “scaling up” itself as a problem (Calvo and Gomila, 2008). Rather we consider it as an opportunity to unearth underlying general principles; that in this way we can bring to light the shared building blocks that allow for the emergence of minimal and yet robust forms of intelligence across living systems. By considering a diverse set of eukaryotes, stronger interferences can be drawn about minimal forms of sensory and perceptual capacities; simple forms of learning (associative and non-associative); varieties of memory; goal-oriented behavior; controlled movement; communication; decision-making; attention; problem solving; survival circuits linked to emotion; and related properties and capacities as realized by different organisms. This is true not only for Drosophila, C. elegans, Aplysia, Arabidopsis, and other models of choice with stars on the Biology Walk of Fame (Lihoreau et al., 2012), but also for organisms less studied and more simple (Moroz, 2009, 2014, 2015; Adamatzky, 2012, 2015; Reid et al., 2012; Kunita et al., 2014; Pagán, 2014). Also these organisms show minimal forms of intelligence based on shared physiology and behavioral traits across eukaryotic living systems (Jennings, 1923; LeDoux, 2012). One nice example of this is the light-induced escape behavior shared between such diverse organisms as Drosophila larvae, nematode C. elegans as well as roots of Arabidopsis and maize (Ward et al., 2008; Xiang et al., 2010; Yokawa et al., 2011, 2013, 2014; Burbach et al., 2012; Bhatla and Horvitz, 2015). Feeding behavior of C. elegans, for instance, appears to be inhibited by hydrogen peroxide produced immediately after illumination (Bhatla and Horvitz, 2015). Similarly, roots of Arabidopsis produce hydrogen peroxide within few seconds after their exposure to light (Yokawa et al., 2011). Illumination stress induces effective light escape tropism in roots (Burbach et al., 2012; Yokawa et al., 2013, 2014). Similar light escape behavior is known to take place also in Drosophila larvae (Keene and Sprecher, 2012; Kane et al., 2013). It is intriguing that evolutionarily very distant organisms living underground in darkness use the same signaling molecule, reactive oxygen species, to change their behavior under illumination. In the particular case of plants, we believe that unveiling why their behavior is so flexible may cast a new light on intelligence in general (Trewavas, 2005, 2009, 2014, 2015). Consider plant anticipatory behavior (Novoplansky, 2009; Shemesh et al., 2010). Our underlying working hypothesis is that adaptive plant behavior can only take place by way of a mechanism that predicts sensory states. The notion of anticipation, however, may come in a variety of forms (Calvo, submitted). Whereas according to weaker readings, anticipatory behavior may rely upon the capacity of the system to model internally environmental sources of stimulation, stronger forms of anticipation that explain away internal modeling cannot be discarded beforehand (Stepp and Turvey, 2010). We may consider “predictive coding” and “strong anticipation” as working hypotheses subject to empirical scrutiny. According to “predictive coding” (Friston, 2012), behavior is to be explained pro-actively. Under a predictive coding reading, a process of probabilistic inference allows animals to scan their surroundings (Kok et al., 2013), estimating the likelihood that some particular state of affairs is the source of stimulation. “Strong anticipation,” by contrast, maintains that predictive success does not involve modeling the future at any stage, but is rather a function of actual past behavior (Stepp and Turvey, 2010; Stepp et al., 2011). In the case of plants, understanding of anticipation in terms of predictive processing calls for studies of how plants model the environmental sources of stimulation. Behavior of plants may thus be equally interpreted pro-actively: plants may be able to estimate the likelihood that one particular state of affairs, and not another, is the cause of its sensory states. A comparative analysis with respect to other eukaryotic life forms is also equally welcome. Plants' directional (tropisms) and non-directional (nastic) responses also probably provide a salient example. The number of growth and movement responses is highest in roots which show gravitropism, phototropism, thigmotropism, chemotropism, oxytropism, halotropism, electrotropism as well as stress avoidance and escape tropisms (Gilroy, 2008; Baluska et al., 2009; Baluška and Mancuso, 2013). Plants live in complex environments and their survival is dependent on reliably sampling critical parameters from their environment using their abundant plant-specific sensory systems, and with sensitivity to particular environmental contexts (Trewavas, 2005, 2009, 2014). In fact, plants and their roots sample more than 20 different parameters from their environment and integrate this complex sensory information online in order to mount appropriate behavioral responses (Knight et al., 1998; Baluska et al., 2009; Hodge, 2009; Trewavas, 2009; Karban and Shiojiri, 2010; Baluška and Mancuso, 2013; Karban et al., 2014; Karban, 2015). It is nonetheless not clear in what sense examples such as these illustrate minimal intelligence. To do so, we must discard the hypothesis that the reaction of plants, animals, fungi or protists to environmental inputs is fully accounted for in terms of hard-wired instincts. Whether anticipation, as observed under tropistic, nastic or any other overt behavioral response in plants, is accounted for in model-based terms or not may have consequences for the way we understand anticipation in “higher” systems. Both empirical and theoretical research approaches on minimal intelligence are needed. It is our conviction that the study of simple forms of behavior from an integral cognitive science perspective, identifying the conditions for minimal intelligence across eukaryote, will allow us to have a more comprehensive picture of what cognition ultimately consists of. Conflict of interest statement The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

          Related collections

          Most cited references46

          • Record: found
          • Abstract: found
          • Article: not found

          The evolution of social behavior in microorganisms.

          Recent studies of microorganisms have revealed diverse complex social behaviors, including cooperation in foraging, building, reproducing, dispersing and communicating. These microorganisms should provide novel, tractable systems for the analysis of social evolution. The application of evolutionary and ecological theory to understanding their behavior will aid in developing better means to control the many pathogenic bacteria that use social interactions to affect humans.
            Bookmark
            • Record: found
            • Abstract: found
            • Article: not found

            Individual differences in reasoning: implications for the rationality debate?

            Much research in the last two decades has demonstrated that human responses deviate from the performance deemed normative according to various models of decision making and rational judgment (e.g., the basic axioms of utility theory). This gap between the normative and the descriptive can be interpreted as indicating systematic irrationalities in human cognition. However, four alternative interpretations preserve the assumption that human behavior and cognition is largely rational. These posit that the gap is due to (1) performance errors, (2) computational limitations, (3) the wrong norm being applied by the experimenter, and (4) a different construal of the task by the subject. In the debates about the viability of these alternative explanations, attention has been focused too narrowly on the model response. In a series of experiments involving most of the classic tasks in the heuristics and biases literature, we have examined the implications of individual differences in performance for each of the four explanations of the normative/descriptive gap. Performance errors are a minor factor in the gap; computational limitations underlie non-normative responding on several tasks, particularly those that involve some type of cognitive decontextualization. Unexpected patterns of covariance can suggest when the wrong norm is being applied to a task or when an alternative construal of the task should be considered appropriate.
              Bookmark
              • Record: found
              • Abstract: found
              • Article: not found

              Light-sensitive neurons and channels mediate phototaxis in C. elegans.

              Phototaxis behavior is commonly observed in animals with light-sensing organs. C. elegans, however, is generally believed to lack phototaxis, as this animal lives in darkness (soil) and does not possess eyes. Here, we found that light stimuli elicited negative phototaxis in C. elegans and that this behavior is important for survival. We identified a group of ciliary sensory neurons as candidate photoreceptor cells for mediating phototaxis. Furthermore, we found that light excited photoreceptor cells by evoking a depolarizing conductance carried by cyclic guanosine monophosphate (cGMP)-sensitive cyclic nucleotide-gated (CNG) channels, revealing a conservation in phototransduction between worms and vertebrates. These results identify a new sensory modality in C. elegans and suggest that animals living in dark environments without light-sensing organs may not be presumed to be light insensitive. We propose that urbilaterians, the last common ancestor of bilaterians, might have already evolved a visual system that employs CNG channels and the second messenger cGMP for phototransduction.
                Bookmark

                Author and article information

                Contributors
                Journal
                Front Psychol
                Front Psychol
                Front. Psychol.
                Frontiers in Psychology
                Frontiers Media S.A.
                1664-1078
                03 September 2015
                2015
                : 6
                : 1329
                Affiliations
                [1] 1MINT Lab, Department of Philosophy, University of Murcia Murcia, Spain
                [2] 2IZMB, University of Bonn Bonn, Germany
                Author notes
                *Correspondence: Paco Calvo, fjcalvo@ 123456um.es

                Edited by: Eddy J. Davelaar, Birkbeck, University of London, UK

                Reviewed by: Leonid L. Moroz, University of Florida, USA

                This article was submitted to Cognitive Science, a section of the journal Frontiers in Psychology

                Article
                10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01329
                4558474
                26388822
                8d134a1e-50d7-41b4-994d-bad65de51435
                Copyright © 2015 Calvo and Baluška.

                This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

                History
                : 05 June 2015
                : 19 August 2015
                Page count
                Figures: 0, Tables: 0, Equations: 0, References: 51, Pages: 4, Words: 2920
                Categories
                Psychology
                Opinion

                Clinical Psychology & Psychiatry
                minimal intelligence,eukaryota,learning,memory,adaptive behavior,decision-making,problem solving

                Comments

                Comment on this article