860
views
0
recommends
+1 Recommend
1 collections
    1
    shares

      If you have found this article useful and you think it is important that researchers across the world have access, please consider donating, to ensure that this valuable collection remains Open Access.

      International Journal of Cuban Studies is published by Pluto Journals, an Open Access publisher. This means that everyone has free and unlimited access to the full-text of all articles from our international collection of social science journalsFurthermore Pluto Journals authors don’t pay article processing charges (APCs).

      scite_
       
      • Record: found
      • Abstract: found
      • Article: found
      Is Open Access

      Game Theory and a New Insight into How the Cuban Missile Crisis Was Resolved

      Published
      research-article
      Bookmark

            Abstract

            The purpose of this article is to investigate the Cuban Missile Crisis with new approaches. For this purpose, we analyse this crisis in two static and dynamic approaches. In the static approach, we look at the crisis through the perspective of credible threats. In the dynamic approach, the crisis is modelled using several game theoretic models. The models allow us to analyse the interplay of the capabilities and the feasibility objectives of each player after a conflict with the other player’s objectives and capabilities. The dynamic system of games has significant implications as an important insight for modelling strategic interactions in which players pursue goals for increasing their personal interests. Our findings give insight into how the two countries reached a compromise in the Cuban Missile Crisis.

            Main article text

            Introduction

            Game theory provides the theoretical underpinnings of analytical techniques and their application in social research. Indeed, many fields of science have benefited from game theoretic models (Askari et al. 2019; Rapoport et al. 1976). Dynamic games provide a framework for modelling the behaviour of players in situations where there are dynamic strategic interactions (Ungureanu 2017; Yeung and Petrosian 2017). Robinson and Goforth (2005) and Van Long (2011) provide surveys of models of dynamic games in industrial organisation. In the Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, Morgenstern and Von Neumann write: “We repeat most emphatically that our theory is thoroughly static. A dynamic theory would unquestionably be more complete and therefore preferable” (1953: 44). Eshaghi and Askari recently introduced a new method of modelling in game theory, named the dynamic system of strategic games (Eshaghi and Askari 2018).

            In a dynamic system of strategic games, such as the game maker game and the strategy-maker game, the pair of rational actions and new properties of games are presented, and with the help of these properties, the dynamics of players’ behaviours are studied. According to this feature, strategic games were divided into two classes, strategy maker games and games that were not strategy maker. Also, both strategy maker games and games that were not strategy maker were themselves divided into two groups. In this article, we present the required concepts and terms, outline some advantages of this modelling, and prove two propositions. Here, we consider strategic 2 × 2 games with perfect information. If a game produces other games, it is called a game maker game. In general, if the games g1,g2,,gn generate games g1,g2,,gn then gi and gi are called producer and produced, respectively. In the dynamic system of games after the choice of strategy or rational action pairs is made by the players by entering into the new games, the productive game is out of reach. Therefore, the producer games are out of reach of the players, and they can influence the selection of strategies and games in the future only as a history of the system. (For more details about the dynamic system of games, refer to Eshaghi and Askari 2018; Eshaghi et al. 2019; Asghari et al. 2021; Babaei and Gordji 2022.)

            As an application of the dynamic system of strategic games, we model the conflict between the Soviet Union and America after the Second World War to October 28, 1962. The Cold War was a state of geopolitical tension after the Second World War between powers in the Eastern Bloc and powers in the Western Bloc. Prior to 1957, Cuba had for many years been under the complete economic and political control of the United States. In late 1956 a revolution to overthrow the Batista regime was initiated by Fidel Castro, which triumphed in 1959. The situation was made more unstable by the unsuccessful US-sponsored Bay of Pigs invasion and a declaration by the Soviet Union of its willingness to aid Cuba in defending itself against the US (Fraser and Hipel 1982; Zagare 2014). Countries like the Soviet Union and the US also belong to different models of international relations and political systems. For modelling the Cuban Missile Crisis, we divide the period into five smaller periods, and in each of those periods we examine static games with perfect information.

            The outline of the article is as follows: in section 2, we introduce the Threat game and credible and non-credible threats. In section 3, we model the conflict between the Soviet Union and the US after the Second World War to October 28, 1962. Section 5 concludes.

            Credible and non-credible threats

            The recently introduced static Threat game is an extension of the Chicken game (Askari et al. 2020). The Threat game has a Nash equilibrium of pure strategy, while the Chicken game has two equilibria with pure strategy. This new game includes three strategies F, T, and TF. In the Threat game, strategy F means any driver doesn’t use the brakes on the route and uses the only steering wheel to pull over, which is an invalid threat (because by holding the steering wheel, the player can swerve to the right or left before the crash). Strategy T means that the player doesn’t use the steering wheel on the route and uses only the brakes to stay on the route, and this is a threat-deterrent (because by using the brakes, the player can stay on the road and not deviate from the path, and the other player must either use the brakes or deviate from the path to avoid an accident or continue on her/his path and lead to an accident). Strategy TF means that the player doesn’t use the steering wheel and brakes on the route and only goes straight, and this is a strictly credible strategy.The Chicken game does not have a dominant strategy, but the Threat game has a dominant strategy.

            Using the new game, the threats were divided into three categories. The first category includes non-credible threats. The term non-credible threat refers to the fact that even if one of the players has threatened the opposite party to use a specific strategy, if there is then a situation where he is forced to put his threat into action, being rational he will not execute the threat (Bolt and Houba 2006; Sun and Sun 2018; Zegart 2020). Threats which are not credible are not worth mentioning because the opposite party does not take them seriously, and therefore they will not have any affect on the change of the opponent’s strategy in the game. The second category includes credible-deterrent threats to deter and prevent struggles, in which a player threatens the opponents to select a strategy in order to warn the opponent, and the opponent believes the player possesses the ability to execute the threat. This is exactly the concept ordinary people apply to nuclear weapons. The weapons are not for attacking, but for deterrence. The third category includes a strictly-credible threat aiming to destroy the opponent, in which case the player has the necessary and sufficient motivation to carry out a threat even if the situation leads to a struggle.

            Since the occurrence of this event 60 years ago, the Cuban Missile Crisis is a case which has been highly important in international affairs, and decision-making theorists and game theorists have made several efforts to analyse it. Well-known theorists such as Schelling, Fraser and Hipel, and Zagari have modelled the Cuban Missile Crisis (Fraser and Hipel 1982; Schelling 1980; Zagare 2014). By analysing the crisis using the Meta-game theory, Howard concluded that the two parties involved in the crisis reached a compromise (Howard 1971). Brams proposed a dynamic modelling framework called Theory of Moves to model this crisis (Brams 1944).

            Here, using the Threat game, we analyse the Cuban Missile Crisis (see Table 1). Conceptually we start the analysis from when the US noticed the construction of missile sites in Cuba. In this game, the US had three strategies: forcing the Soviet Union to eliminate its missiles through mass media (S), blockade Cuba and seek a solution through diplomatic channels (B), and attacking Cuba (SB). The Soviet Union had three strategies: announcing that it sought to intensify the hostilities (S), keeping the missiles there and searching for a solution through diplomatic channels (B), or attacking the US (SB).

            Table 1

            Threat game

            In this game, iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies allows us to solve the game. For both players, SB is strictly dominated by (B). By eliminating this strategy, players have two strategies, S and B. Now for both players, S is strictly dominated by B. So the game equilibrium is (B.B), that is, the two countries use a credible-deterrent strategy to prevent an atomic war. In other words, the blockade of Cuba by the US and keeping the missiles there by the Soviet Union, along with the use of a diplomatic channel, was the same as engaging a brake against atomic war by both players. Therefore, this static analysis gives a logical insight as to why the two countries reached a compromise in the Cuban Missile Crisis.

            Analysis of the Cuban Missile Crisis with a dynamic approach

            The Soviet Union and US relations after the Second World War were sometimes strained. But the most important and dangerous crisis in the Soviet Union and US relations, which put the world on the edge of a devastating war, followed the establishment of Soviet missile bases in Cuba. The Soviet Union wanted to establish a massive arsenal of heavy weapons there in order to become the largest military station in the Caribbean. But Khrushchev’s trick was ultimately revealed. In October 1962 a US spy plane discovered a missile launch site to the west of Havana, which confirmed the establishment of medium-range missiles in Cuba (May and Zelikow 2002). To confront the danger of that threat to US security, the president convoked a war council, and for one week a serious and secret discussion was held in the White House. In this council, different suggestions were proposed, including bombing the missile launch platform, or an all-out military attack on Cuba and military occupation of the country. On 22 October 1962 Kennedy then informed the American people that the Soviet government had established missile bases in Cuba, a distance of one hundred miles from American beaches, and warned them that this presented a threat to the country’s security. In the same announcement he told the Soviet government that it must remove its missile bases from Cuba. Following this, he issued an order for a naval blockade of Cuba to prevent the transfer of the Soviet’s new missile equipment to Cuba (Kennedy 1969). This issue became a world crisis for one week. (For more information about the Cuban Missile Crisis, see Blaschke 2016; Crall and Martin 2013; and Gibson 2012.)

            In this section, we propose a different model from the static one-play interaction of the Soviet Union and the US in in the Cuban Missile Crisis. Now we will use a dynamic system of games to model the relations between the Soviet Union and the US after the Second World War leading up to October 28, 1962. To this end, we divide the period into five smaller periods, and in each of those periods we examine static games with perfect information. The first period is from the end of the Second World War to October 13, 1962, which is represented by game g1. The second period from October 14 to 22 is represented by games g2 and g3. The third period is from October 23 to 25 and is represented by games g4, g5, g6 and g7. The fourth period is from October 26 to 27 and is represented by games g8 and g9. And finally, the day of October 28 is represented by game g10.

            Relations between the Soviet Union and the US after the Second World War and during the 1950s constituted a Deadlock game in which they manifested minimal desire to cooperate with each other. As a result, both countries selected the non-cooperation strategy. The Deadlock game g1 is shown in Figure 1. The row player (player 1) is the Soviet Union and the column player (player 2) is the US. The players’ set of actions include cooperation 1C and defect 1D. Players’ preferences in this node are the same order preferences of strategic game g1. The game’s Nash equilibrium is (1D,1D). In g1, dominant action 1D1 is defect and dominated action 1C1 is cooperation for player 1. Also, this game has a dominant action of defect 1D2 and dominated action of cooperation 1C2 for player 2. In other words, game g1 is an action maker of order (2, 2). The only pair of rational actions for the players is (1D,1D)1,2. Based on the players being rational, they select dominant action 1D1 and dominant action 1D2 for the continuation of the game. According to its dominant action, the Soviets were convinced in July 1962 to implement their Atomic Missile Establishment plan in Cuba in order to confront the US’s growing expansion.

            Figure 1

            Dynamic system of games between the Soviet Union and the US.

            Action 1D1 leads to Hostage game g2. The Soviet Union wanted to surprise the US. In this game, the Soviet Union has two possible actions: either cooperate 2C through removing the missiles or defect 2D and maintain the missiles. The US could reveal the issue 2C or keep it secret 2D . The game Nash equilibrium is (2D,2D) . This game has a dominant action of defect 2D1 and a dominated action of cooperation 2C1 for player 1. The dominant action 2C2 for player 2 is revealing the issue and the dominated action 2D2 is keeping it secret. The only pair of rational actions for both players is (2D,2C)1,2.

            Action 1D2 leads to the Self-Serving game g3. In g3 the US has two actions: either it cooperates 3C by doing nothing or it defects 3D through a blockade of Cuba. The Soviet Union also has two actions: either it cooperates 3C to remove missiles through the diplomatic channel or it defects 3D and maintains the missiles. The game Nash equilibrium is (3C,3D). Game g3 is action maker of order (2, 1). This game has a dominant action of defect 3D1,2 and a dominated action of cooperation 3C1,2 for player 2. Pairs of rational actions for the players are (3C,3D)1,2 and (3D,3D)1.

            Action 2D1 leads to the Chicken game g4. In g4 the Soviet Union has two possible actions: either it does not attack the US 4C or it attacks the US 4D. The US has two possible actions: either it does not attack the Soviet Union 4C or it attacks the Soviet Union for retaliation 4D. The game Nash equilibria are (4C,4D) and (4D,4C). Game g4 is action maker of order (2, 0). In other words, this game is not action maker for the players. The players’ pairs of rational actions are (4C,4C)1,2, (4D,4C)1 and (4C,4D)2.

            Action 2C2 leads to the Stag Hunt game g5. In g5 the US has two possible actions: either through diplomacy it seeks a solution 5C or through diplomacy it puts pressure on the Soviet Union 5D. The Soviet Union has two possible actions: either it seeks a solution 5C through diplomacy or it thinks about crisis intensification 5D. The game Nash equilibria are (5C, 5C) and (5D, 5D). Game g5 is action maker of order (2, 0). The players’ pair of rational actions are (5C, 5C)1,2 and (5D, 5D)1,2.

            The pair of rational actions (3C, 3D)1 leads to another Stag Hunt game g6. In g6 the Soviet Union has two possible actions: either it does not break the blockade 6C or it breaks the blockade 6D. The US has two possible actions: either it does not have a conflict 6C with the Soviet ships or it has a conflict with the Soviet ships 6D. The game Nash equilibria are (6C, 6C) and (6D, 6D). Game g6 is action maker of order (2, 0). The players’ pair of rational actions are (6C, 6C)1,2 and (6D, 6D)1,2.

            Action 3D2 leads to Chicken game g7. In g7 the US has two possible actions: either it does not attack the Soviet Union 7C or it attacks the Soviet Union 7D. The Soviet Union has two possible actions: either it does not attack the US 7C or it attacks the US in a retaliatory invasion 7D. The game Nash equilibria are (7C, 7D) and (7D,7C). Game g7 is action maker of order (2, 0). The players’ pairs of rational actions are (7C, 7C)1,2, (7D, 7C)1 and (7C, 7D)2.

            Based on players’ rationality and strategic preferences, players selecting pairs of rational actions (4C, 4C)1,2, (5C, 5C)1,2 and (6C, 6C)1,2 move to Coordination game g8. In g8 the Soviet Union has two possible actions: either it issues the command for its ships not to move toward Cuba 8C or it thinks about resolving the crisis through negotiation 8D. The US has two possible actions: either it issues the command that its ships not confront the Soviet ships 8C or it thinks about resolving the crisis through negotiation 8D. The game Nash equilibria are (8C, 8C) and (8D, 8D). Game g8 is action maker of order (2, 0). The players’ pairs of rational actions are (8C, 8C)1,2 and (8D, 8D)1,2.

            Based on players’ rationality and strategic preferences, players selecting pairs of rational actions (5C, 5C)1,2, (6C, 6C)1,2 and (7C, 7C)1,2 move to game g9. In g9 the Soviet Union has two possible actions: either it removes the missiles from Cuba 9C or it maintains the missiles in Cuba 9D. The US has two possible actions: either it removes its blockade of Cuba 9C or maintains its blockade of Cuba 9D. The game Nash equilibria are (9C, 9C) and (9D, 9D). Game g9 is action maker of order (2, 2). In g9 the weak dominant action 9C1 for the Soviet Union is removing the missiles and its weakly dominated action 9D1 is maintaining the missiles. For the US the weakly dominant action 9C2 is removing its blockade and the weakly dominated action 9D2 is maintaining its blockade. The players’ pairs of rational actions are (9C, 9C)1,2, (9D, 9D)1,2, (9D, 9C)1 and (9C, 9D)2.

            Based on players’ rationality and strategic preferences, players selecting pairs of rational actions (8C, 8C)1,2 and (9C, 9C)1,2 move to Win-Win game g10. In this game both players have two possible actions, cooperation 10C and defection 10D. The game Nash equilibrium is (10C, 10C). With this the players have no desire to continue and so this completes the system.

            The dynamic system of games with strategic games between the Soviet Union and the US is represented by the graph in Figure 1. The history of the system is as follows.

            In Figure 1, if the Chicken game had a dominant action even for one player, an atomic war would probably have occurred. This weakness of not having the dominant action in this game causes the players to consider their strategic preferences and not to use tactical preferences inside the game. In other words, players prefer strategic preferences over tactical preferences. Recognising this is important for understanding why the two countries reached a compromise in the Cuban Missile Crisis.

            Conclusion

            A dynamic system of games helps us to analyse an event by dividing it into different periods and dynamically using several games. This enables the event analyst to evaluate the decisions and strategies that the players have chosen in order to achieve a reasonable and acceptable result. The system also shows the impact of players’ decisions on each other, and the impact of the results from one period on the results of subsequent periods.

            In this study, we used a dynamic system of strategic games to investigate the interaction between the Soviet Union and the US from the end of the Second World War until October 28, 1962, that is, up to the end of the Cuban Missile Crisis. A dynamic system of games is a combination of dynamic and static interactive situations that are moving forward. In our case we divided the full time interval into five periods, and in each period we reviewed static games with complete information. Each country, based on its forces and capabilities, sought to achieve its goals and objectives in Cuba. The result of the dynamic game was that the countries reached a compromise, as in fact occurred in history. Looking at the strategies adopted in each period, we can see what sorts of strategies have the potential to achieve such a compromise. Thinking about other cases of conflict beyond the case we examined, this study shows how a dynamic system of strategic games can provide a frame for analysing what sorts of cooperative behaviours among players can potentially yield an exit from the conflict.

            Notes

            1.

            Somayeh Shaabani is a PhD Candidate and teaching assistant in the Faculty of Mathematics, Statistics and Computer Science at Semnan University in Semnan, Iran. Madjid Eshaghi Gordji is a Professor of Mathematics at Semnan University in Semnan, Iran.

            References

            1. (2021) “Modelling US-China relationship: a game theory perspective”. International Journal of Nonlinear Analysis and Applications 12(2): 1371–82.

            2. (2019) “The behavioral model and game theory”. Palgrave Communication 5(57): 1–8.

            3. (2020) “Game theory and trade tensions between advanced economies”. European Research Studies Journal, 23 (Special issue 1): 50–65.

            4. (2022) “Modeling political and economic relations between Norway and Russia: A behavioral game theory approach”. The Pure and Applied Mathematics 29(2): 141–60.

            5. (2016) “Running the Cold War: gender, race, and track in cultural diplomacy, 1955–1975”. Diplomatic History 40(5): 826–44.

            6. (2006) Credible Threats in Negotiations: A Game-Theoretic Approach. Cham: Springer Science & Business Media.

            7. (1944) Theory of Moves. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

            8. (2013) “Cool hand nuke: lessons from the quiet diplomacy of the Cienfuegos non-crisis”. Foreign Policy Analysis 9(2): 189–201.

            9. (2018) “Dynamic system of strategic games”. International Journal of Nonlinear Analysis and Applications, 9(1): 83–98.

            10. (2019) “Modeling political and economic relations between Russia and Turkey: a game theory approach”. International Journal of Computer Science and Network Security 19(2): 163.

            11. (1982) “Dynamic modelling of the Cuban missile crisis”. Conflict Management and Peace Science 6(2): 1–18.

            12. (2012) Talk at the Brink: Deliberation and Decision during the Cuban Missile Crisis. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

            13. (1971) Paradoxes of Rationality: Games, Metagames, and Political Behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

            14. (1969) 13 Days: The Cuban Missile Crisis October 1962. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

            15. (eds) (2002) The Kennedy Tapes: Inside the White House during the Cuban Missile Crisis. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

            16. (1953) Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

            17. (1976) The 2 × 2 Games. Ann Arbor: Michigan University Press.

            18. (2005) The Topology of the 2 x 2 Games: A New Periodic Table. Vol. 3. New York: Psychology Press.

            19. (1980) The Strategy of Conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

            20. (2018) “Credible commitment and credible threat in games”, in , Management Game Theory. Singapore: Springer, 63–7.

            21. (2017) “Dynamic contracting under permanent and transitory private information”. International Journal of Game Theory 46(3): 667–92.

            22. (2011) “Dynamic games in the economics of natural resources: a survey”. Dynamic Games and Applications 1(1): 115–48.

            23. (2017) “Infinite horizon dynamic games: a new approach via information updating”. International Game Theory Review 19(04): 1–23.

            24. (2014) “A game-theoretic history of the Cuban Missile Crisis”. Economies 2(1): 20–44.

            25. (2020) “Cheap fights, credible threats: the future of armed drones and coercion”. Journal of Strategic Studies 43(1): 6–46.

            Author and article information

            Journal
            10.13169/intljofdissocjus
            International Journal of Cuban Studies
            IJCS
            Pluto Journals
            1756-3461
            1756-347X
            31 May 2023
            2023
            : 15
            : 1
            : 39-49
            Affiliations
            [1 ]Semnan University, Iran, Semnan University, Iran
            Article
            10.13169/intejcubastud.15.1.0039
            3062c252-ae68-4258-afe8-857bcca5a4b1
            Copyright 2023, Somayeh Shaban and Madjid Eshaghi Gordji

            This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Licence (CC BY) 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/, which permits unrestricted use, distribution and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited.

            History
            Page count
            Pages: 11
            Categories
            Academic articles

            Literary studies,Arts,Social & Behavioral Sciences,History,Cultural studies,Economics
            rationality,dynamic system of games,credible threats,international relations,Cuban Missile Crisis,prediction

            Comments

            Comment on this article